Tuesday, August 20, 2019
Behavior :: essays research papers
EDUCATING ETHICAL BEHAVIOR: ARISTOTLEââ¬â¢S VIEWS ON AKRASIA ââ¬Å"Can the teaching of ethics really help cleanse the business world of shady dealings?â⬠Asked by Newsweek magazine during the height of the recent Wall-Street scandals,1 this query resonates with perennial concerns about whether or not virtue can be taught and how such instruction might best be effected. The problem, Newsweek declares, is not that students lack ethical standards or are incapable of distinguishing wrong from right. The challenge for educators rather lies in helping students act on the virtues they espouse. ââ¬Å"Even in todayââ¬â¢s complex world, knowing whatââ¬â¢s right is comparatively easy,â⬠Newsweek concludes. ââ¬Å"Itââ¬â¢s doing whatââ¬â¢s right thatââ¬â¢s hard.â⬠Why do people act wrongly, when they know full well what right conduct demands? This phenomenon, known to philosophers as incontinence or akrasia, receives extensive treatment in Book Seven of Aristotleââ¬â¢s Nicomachean Ethics.2 Like Newsweek, Aristotle holds that akrasia presents a special challenge for moral education. How does Aristotle conceive this challenge, and what might contemporary educators learn from Aristotleââ¬â¢s analysis? To appreciate Aristotleââ¬â¢s insights into akrasia and moral instruction, it is helpful to begin by looking at popular views of the akraticââ¬â¢s dilemma. Popular beliefs about incontinence are varied and often contradictory, Aristotle contends.3 Two, however, bear scrutiny. Aristotle summarizes them as follows: (1) The continent person seems to be the same as one who abides by his rational calculation; and the incontinent person seems to be the same as one who abandons it. (2) The incontinent person knows that his actions are base, but does them because of his feelings, while the continent person knows that his appetites are base, but because of reason does not follow them.4 In short, popular opinion concludes that with respect to akrasia, feeling overpowers reason; the individual, as a consequence, is seduced into acting irrationally. This conclusion, in turn, is marked by two deeper suppositions: a) feeling (or appetite) is distinct from reason; b) reason can be disciplined, but feelings cannot. Although voiced in ancient Greece, these common beliefs about akrasia are held no less widely today. Like Aristotleââ¬â¢s compatriots, we tend to divorce reason from desires and appetites. The latter we regard as urges we cannot help but feel; reason, by contrast, bespeaks a capacity for considered control. When we act against our better judgment, it is because we cannot hold our feelings at bay. We lose control and behave irrationally.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment